A few happy things to report.
The first is that my brother married Emily on Saturday and it was a wonderful day. For the first time I have a sister!
The second is that my paper "Realising International Justice" is available as an advance viewing. In the paper I argue that the requirements of background justice require the global taxation of international citizens, but that this does not require the creation of a global state or for all states to impose the same tax rates. Instead, I suggest that the employment of a counter-incentive would achieve the desired ends. I also explain my counter-incentive proposal in a book chapter published last year and in chapter eight my forthcoming book, Rethinking Taxation.
If you work at a university you might want to ask your librarians to subscribe if they do not already receive the Moral and Political Philosophy journal as part of a package. It should develop into an important journal in the field, and mine is the second paper it has made available.
Tuesday, 25 February 2014
Thursday, 16 January 2014
Land Value Taxation, part 2: Why arguments for the LVT don’t work
In a blog earlier this week I explained how changes
to the tax regime can create windfalls or immediate costs to owners of the
types of property affected by the change. For example, a tax on housing will
hit the owners of housing at the time the tax is announced as their asset will immediately
drop in value in line with the newly increased tax.
I’m sure those of you who have read my previous post
explaining the LVT can all work out where I am going with this. If an LVT is
introduced it will reduce the expected income on rented land; more of the
rental income than expected will be lost to the tax. Similarly, for people who
own and use land their cost for continuing to use the land will immediately
rise. Buyers will not be willing to pay as much as they will now expect to pay
the tax in order to enjoy the use or investment income from the land. These
future owners will not pay anything as the result of the introduction of the
tax, nor will the past owners who sold up before the announcement.
For this reason, a big question for supporters of the LVT is
whether to compensate owners of land upon the introduction of the tax. This was
considered, for example, by J.S. Mill back in his 1848 economics textbook. A
pure version of the LVT would provide this compensation in order to ensure that
the tax only falls on those who might benefit from increases in the value of land. However, if the government
compensates landowners it will suddenly need to find a huge amount of revenue
which will only be repaid over a number of years. Government revenues will take
a huge hit in the short and medium term and the LVT will not bring in any
substantial revenue for many years. This leaves the government to rely on loans
and other taxes in the short term.
This also means that all the increases in land values that
occurred up to the introduction of the tax are not taxed by the pure LVT. To
make matters worse, if land values don’t increase after this point, then it
will take ever longer to repay the debts taken on. Supporters of LVT tend to
assume land will always increase in value, but this is much more likely if
there is an overall increase in productivity and population (or that the
increase in one over-rides the drop in the other).
The “pure” version of LVT would therefore raise much less
revenue than the “impure” version, which can be considered a wealth tax. I have
argued in a previous post that wealth taxes are generally regrettable, though
they might be acceptable in some cases. However, the impure LVT is even more troubling than other forms of
wealth tax. This is because it is a discriminatory
wealth tax. I refer to it as such because the tax only falls on those who hold
a particular kind of wealth, namely land.
Consider a group of imaginary people to see the problem. Take four economically fortunate individuals who have various forms of investments, and two less economically fortunate individuals who have scrimped and saved in order to purchase some land. Anna, Bernie, Celine and Daryl all receive a significant inheritance (in an unjust society where inheritances are entirely untaxed), while Enid and Fred are diligent savers investing for their impending retirement. Anna and Bernie inherit a large amount of land while Celine and Daryl inherit money. Bernie sells his land to Fred and invests in other things, while Daryl decides to purchase land with his inheritance. Enid, meanwhile, invests in the stock market. Then the government suddenly announced an impure LVT.
Anna, Daryl and Fred face an immediate loss in the value of
their investment. Meanwhile Bernie, Celine and Enid are entirely unaffected.
This imposes a wealth tax on those who are unlucky enough to have chosen to
invest in a particular kind of investment. Some of those taxed were
economically fortunate, but Fred was not. Furthermore, some of the most
fortunate people are unaffected, even if their good fortune arrived in the
shape of gifted land. The introduction of the impure LVT is like a game of
musical chairs, whereby those left holding the land at the time in question
lose out.
One argument that I have seen in favour of a land tax is
that land should not have been privately owned in the first place—it has been
stolen from the community and those who benefit from this theft can have no
complaint if their investment loses value. The problem with this argument is
that Bertie gained from the supposedly unjust theft of land—his family were
landowners for centuries—but he did not pay any of the tax. Bernie sold his
land to poor old Fred. Fred did not gain from the land; he merely lost his
retirement investment. Meanwhile Bernie got away with a land-based fortune
intact. I don’t agree with the idea that landowners are in a morally more
questionable position than others (though it is true that most of the
landowners in England and Scotland in the past centuries got it through very
questionable means).
If we wish to tax the previously undertaxed wealth of the
economically fortunate a more comprehensive wealth tax would be much more
principled than an LVT. The pure LVT will raise very limited revenue and fail to
tax those who benefitted from land and economic fortune in the past if it is
pure. Furthermore, the impure LVT should be rejected as a very blunt and
discriminatory wealth tax that will also fail to fall consistently on those who
have benefitted from either land or good economic fortune.
This only leaves the argument for the LVT that in the longer
term it will tax those who benefit from the increased prosperity of the whole
community. This occurs because the increased wealth in the community will
translate to more valuable land. However, if this is the basis for taxing land then a comprehensive acquired
income tax of the kind I propose in chapter four of my forthcoming book, Rethinking Taxation, is much a better
option. This would take into account the profits that people make on any
investment. It would therefore fall on all
those who gain from increased prosperity, not just on the landowners who
benefit from it.
Wednesday, 15 January 2014
On Land Value Tax (LVT), Part 1.
The longstanding tax proposal for LVT was reasonably popular
in the late 1800s and still has some advocates today. I will explain the LVT,
explain its advantages and disadvantages. In the following blog I will provide
a further argument against it, referring to a couple of my previous blogs, to
show that LVT is in fact a very limited and partial form of wealth tax.
The idea behind the LVT is fairly simple; tax the rental
value of the land that people own. There are many variants of the proposal, but
the most sensible approach is to focus on the value that the land would have if
it were sold without any development on it, and then the owner would be charged
a proportion of this value each year. This requires the land to be valued
regularly.
LVT-type proposals were generally advocated by classical
economists such as Adam Smith, David Ricardo and JS Mill, who saw land as a
separate category. Popular political thinkers such as Thomas Paine and Henry
George argued for the proposal, but obviously ran up against landed interests.
These thinkers perhaps realised that landowners got money for their land
without having to do anything, and realised that taxing the land would not
produce any economic disincentives—landowners would need to use the land
productively but now to pay the tax instead of to enrich themselves.
Classical economists saw land as a separate economic
category with its own economic nature. However, the marginal revolution in
economic thinking did away with this categorisation. According to
post-classical (including of course neo-classical) economists economic
decisions are (or perhaps should be?) based on the marginal benefits of one
economic use when compared to others. The upshot was that land was treated just
the same as any other economic resource (or input, or “factor of production”).
The case for treating land any differently disappears if we
point out that there is nothing particularly special about land as an economic
factor. Economic theories that can fully explain economic decisions about land
without creating an additional category are going to be more attractive than
those which depend on extra categories. One defence of LVT is to insist that
classical economics is uniquely correct, and this is the recourse of the
commentator on this blog “Physiocrat” who has commented on several of my
previous posts. It is an interesting project to consider what has been lost in
the shift from classical to marginal economics, but I do not think that the
treatment of land as a special economic category is one of the losses.
I have said repeatedly that taxation is a normative issue
and this is where the real action lies. I have argued that taxes should be
judged on their incidence with regard to the economically fortunate/unfortunate
and their likely economic effects, and LVT does fairly well on this count.
However, it taxes only those fortunate people who have a prior investment in
land, as I will explain further in the following post. Taxing people who have
good economic fortune in a more systematic manner through the imposition of a
tax on comprehensive income, particularly on windfall income, would be much
more appropriate. LVT fails to tax the recipients of gifts, inheritances, and
returns to scarce talents. Fortunate people who have investments in government
or corporate bonds will be relatively unaffected by the switch to LVT.
However, there is a political philosophy which supports the
imposition of LVT on normative grounds; Left libertarianism. This view has been
defended by political philosophers such as Hilel Steiner (see An Essay on Rights) and Mike Otsuka (Libertarianism without Inequality). The
idea is that people own themselves, and therefore the products of their labour
(so far so libertarian). However, people cannot come to own land, since this is
for the benefit of the whole community. Therefore, when people take ownership
of land they owe the community rent from taking temporary ownership of this
communal resource.
This position is a perfectly philosophically valid, but I’m
not convinced that such strong self-ownership rights exist, nor that it is that
important to enforce them in such a stringent way. The division between the
treatment of the self and the treatment of land seems arbitrary to me in this instance.
Of course, we have reasons to limit what can be done to persons in ways that do
not apply to land, but taxing people on the returns to their labour does not
trouble me that people are being violated in any way. Slightly less strong rights of ownership seem to provide all
the personal freedom that people need.
I’m not convinced by the economic arguments or philosophical
ones for LVT, and I will add a further important point about the introduction
of an LVT in my next post.
Monday, 13 January 2014
Tax incidence and legislation change
In a previous
blog I set out my approach to taxation. What matters is the incidence of taxation and where possible
this should fall on the most economically fortunate members of society. In this
blog I wish to emphasise an important point about how changes to tax rules create windfalls for, or costs to, taxpayers.
This means that the incidence of the tax system may not fall on the intended
groups in the aftermath of such changes.
This point was emphasised in an address given over one
hundred years ago by the economist Edwin Seligman. Much of
this address is aimed at attacking the somewhat silly views of taxation from
what he calls the perspective of the individual: taxation according to the
benefit principle or ability to pay principle. Despite his warnings these views
have remained popular with tax lawyers and economists through to this day.
(Murphy and Nagel in The Myth of
Ownership have in this century done a good job of attacking these views of
taxation and we can but hope that writers on taxation will take notice at some
point). Seligman wants to focus on the place of taxation within society as a
whole, which is a much more satisfactory perspective. The tax system has to be
justified to all, taxpayers and benefit recipients alike, and this needs to be
done through a theory of justice. In the course of his address on this subject
Seligman makes a very important point about the incidence of taxation, which I
will describe here.
Seligman pointed out that we need to take account of the shifting and diffusion and capitalization
and absorption of taxation. The
rational price of an investment, or factor of production, or whatever, will
take account of the expected tax which it will attract. This is the
capitalization aspect. So if a new tax is levied on a particular kind of
investment (in Seligman’s example a bond), or the rate of an existing tax is
increased, then this will be passed on to the capitalized market value of the
bond. So the person who is holding the bond when the change takes place will
take an immediate hit on the value of the bond. It will be absorbed into the new price. Previous owners of the bond are
unaffected, as are future owners. This is because past owners have already sold
at the previous capitalization and future owners will buy it at the new
capitalization rate.
The idea of shifting is that people will pass on some taxes
to others, so that a special tax on housing will fall on housing owners.
However, as a result of this people will stop investing in housing until rents
or values rise to cover the cost of the tax. In the meantime, the tax will therefore
fall primarily on people who build houses and provide goods and services to
house builders (or the investors in and workers of these companies). The tax is
therefore diffused onto many people
instead of the owner of the primary item.
In both cases this leads to the disappearance or vanishing
of the tax. The increase in tax is a heavy burden on some existing owners but
does not create a permanent burden on such owners. The tax may fall on other,
unintended groups and individuals, as well. When creating or increasing taxes,
these changes should be borne in mind, since the increase may act as a kind of
wealth tax, something I will write about in another blog.
Of course, this point goes the other way. Removing tax or lowering
the rate on existing taxes can create windfalls
to owners. If someone buys something at a market value where there is an
expectation of a certain amount of taxation and the taxation is dropped, the
owner immediately has something they can sell for a larger amount. The
potential to create windfalls is something to which we all need to be aware.
Governments are therefore going to be constantly lobbied to
allow special exemptions and for the dropping of taxes which will create an immediate windfall to whoever happens to
own the item at that point in time. In states where corruption is relatively
difficult lobbying of this kind will be one of the easiest ways to make a quick
windfall. Governments may be enticed to bribe strategically important voter
groups (more likely in the UK due its archaic democracy) and political parties
may be able to offer corporations and the wealthy artificial windfalls in
exchange for campaign donations (more likely in the US due to its ridiculous
rules on political party funding).
Failures to collect tax also create windfalls. An example of
this is the Vodafone Mannesmann deal, over which Vodafone could have expected
to pay several billion pounds in tax. Through questionable accounting (via
Switzerland and Luxembourg), Vodafone paid very little tax and for some unknown
reason HMRC officials made a deal with Vodafone that enabled them to pay a
fraction of the expected amount. This was a pure windfall to Vodafone
shareholders and a pure loss to the rest of the UK who would benefit from the
government spending (or debt alleviation) that would have followed from the tax
revenues. Of course, other corporations will then ask that they can have the
same favourable tax treatment. This bizarre decision, described in Richard
Brooks’ book the Great Tax Robbery,
was an absolute scandal.
Given these temptations, right-thinking citizens must remain
vigilant that governments and their agents are not falling prey to the
promotion of the interests of the few at the expense of the many. Tax windfalls
of this kind will usually benefit people who are among the least deserving of state help. Tax reductions may sometimes be
advisable, but they should always be undertaken with the utmost caution.
Friday, 10 January 2014
Market society and market fundamentalism
Continuing the theme of my previous blogs this week I wanted to say
something further about market institutions and the tendency towards market fundamentalist (or
libertarian) thinking. I have said that the market economy is the only way to
secure economic prosperity and freedom. It’s the only economic game in town as
it incentivises people to work, save and innovate. Markets also automatically
facilitate the exchange of huge amounts of information through constantly shifting
prices. However, I have also said that market prices lead some people to an
“everyday libertarianism” whereby people think that pre-tax exchanges are in
some way just or correct.
It is important that, as Michael
Sandel puts it, we do not move from a market economy with useful market
institutions to a market society.
This is a society in which everything is valued through the lens of market
interaction. This is hardly a novel thought; it has been presented in many
forms by religious preachers, Marxists (including Marx), and many political
philosophers (such as Deborah
Satz). However, even though there are big differences between my views and
those of these thinkers, the basic shared point needs to be repeated regularly for
reasons that are apparent from my previous blogs. This is that market institutions
can lead to this everyday libertarianism or market fundamentalism.
Resources should
be valued in accordance with their market value when they are exchanged or when
taxation is calculated. The market value of items of property will represent
the scarcity of their component parts and the cost of putting them together and
transporting them. People should have to pay this amount. However, that does
not mean that people should only value themselves or the resources they might
obtain for what others will pay for them.
It is a real shame when people judge themselves according to
the money they make in the labour (or even investment) markets. Markets are
competitive and often where one person wins another person loses; we can’t all
win. If people judge themselves according to their market earnings then many
people will feel inferior not because they are incapable but because they are slightly
less capable (or in some cases less fortunate in their social connections or
simply not being in the right place at the right time).
If we want to use market values to judge the contribution
that we ourselves or other people make to society then market prices are useful
up to a point. After all, if someone is performing unpopular and socially
valued labour then they usually will be financially rewarded. And if someone is
inventing or investing in useful products then they should receive a good return.
However, market returns do not always indicate contribution. People can
contribute in ways that aren’t rewarded by the market, such as volunteering,
performing services in their local community, and caring for relatives or
neighbours. Conversely, markets can provide handsome rewards for behaviour that
makes little or no contribution; if some captures a monopoly (such as Bill
Gates with Microsoft), obtains rent on something they did not pay much—or
anything—for, or if they take advantage of a strong bargaining position then
they are not really contributing as much as the money indicates. Market
outcomes do not tell us much about a person.
Regarding the resources themselves, people will hopefully
value these resources for their ability to help them live their life in the way
that they wish. The market value simply represents the opportunity cost to
other people of those resources. If market fundamentalism takes hold, however,
people may come to value resources for their market value alone rather than
what they can do for people. If this happens then people engage in unproductive
and bizarre behaviour, such as seeking resources to use as status symbols for
display to others rather than resources which provide some kind of benefit to
their holder. The desire for status is very prominent in the human psyche, but
it is a zero sum game in that one person’s plus point is another person’s minus
point. This point has also been made by utilitarians such as Richard
Layard. It can be even worse than this as the misery of those with status
anxiety probably outweighs the happiness benefits that the fortunate obtain
(not that I think everything should be evaluated on the basis of the happiness
caused, of course).
Of course, being a liberal I’m not going to suggest that someone should be unable to use her resources to attempt to buy a feeling of superiority; that’s
entirely up to her. What I am pointing out is that (very positive) market
institutions can lead towards (very negative) market fundamentalism and that right-thinking
people need to take note of this phenomenon and resist it. I don’t agree with
radicals that this unfortunate tendency overrides the benefits of the market
economy—there aren’t any better proposals to organise an economy. Nor do I
think it is the job of the state to counteract the tendency. Rather, it is the
job of all of us to ensure that we are not ensnared by this kind of thinking.
We can also challenge others who attempt to impress through the purchase and
display of status items; it don’t impress us much.
Thursday, 9 January 2014
Libertarian myths
In my previous blogs I have emphasised a libertarian myth;
the everyday libertarian myth. This could be alternatively described as the
myth of the free market outcome; that people should receive whatever the market
would provide them with minimal interference by the state. We could also call this "free market fundamentalism." Rather than simply viewing the market as a a vitally important and useful institution, the fundamentalist thinks that free market outcomes are somehow correct outcomes with some kind of inherent moral value.
A further libertarian myth to expose mutually supports the
free market fundamentalism. This is the myth of the economically isolated
individual. Political philosophers such as Hobbes and Locke have made much use
of isolated individuals in order to consider the legitimacy of the state. Some,
such as Nozick, have applied this line of argument to the justification of the
distribution of goods as well. However, it is important to emphasise that the
distribution of goods has to be justified to all members of society. The focus
on the idea of an isolated individual is completely inappropriate in this
setting.
People are not isolated; humans are completely dependent
on others for the first several years of their lives. Even beyond that point,
our sense of ourselves as humans comes from our social interactions with
others. A human raised by animals would probably not be recognised as human.
There are of course the few historical cases where people have found themselves
living somewhere where they are able to survive despite the fact they have no
interaction with others. The classic example is the shipwreck victim on an
unpopulated island. Such examples are extremely rare but such stories—real or fictional—are very popular. However, even this person takes with them their previous
human capital and whatever technologies and equipment they have with them.
We might accept that the individual in the lonely island
case is fully entitled to what they find or make, though this raises questions
about global justice that I will not consider here. The point I wish to
emphasise is that humans are part of a society and the rules of entitlement
should be developed with that social interaction in mind, albeit with respect
for each individual member of that society. What an individual might be able to
get if their society was viewed as many one-person economic islands should have
no influence on what an individual should receive in a society.
The myth of the economically isolated individual is regrettable
and should not have any influence on anything. Yet it seems to underpin many
people’s thinking (particularly in the USA). Political philosophy depends on
artificial examples, and I have no problem with using them in arguments.
However, while these examples and illustrations and powerful their use is limited to the particular argument they are designed to support. The idea of the economically isolated human has been taken
outside its immediate contextual usefulness and used to bolster an otherwise
unpalatable free-market ideology.
Should we tax wealth?
The idea of taxing wealth seems to be discussed more often
as government revenues drop and austerity begins to bite. Wealth taxes appear
to be attractive as a way to provide public funds without causing too much
economic damage; it may reduce the quantity of resources available for
investment but it does not seem that much investment is being used for
innovation anyway. A one-off, entirely unexpected, wealth tax would not cause
any major change in economic behaviour (though a lot of discussion about it
might). Most of those considering the merits of a wealth tax will think that
the wealthy should have been taxed at much higher rates than they have been
previously, and so a wealth tax appears attractive on many counts.
The practical case against wealth taxes is that they
discourage people from investing. If people expect a wealth tax in the future
they may decide simply to spend money earlier (since many wealthy people would
probably choose to have something—even if it is relatively pointless—in preference
to having nothing for him and more for the government). Wealth taxes cause
additional uncertainty and anxiety for investors, and may result in wealthier
people taking even greater care to hide their wealth than they already do. The
practical arguments for the occasional wealth tax may or may not outweigh the
practical arguments against, but normative issues are of course paramount.
My
view is that taxes should fall where possible on the more economically
fortunate and this may appear to be a good argument for wealth taxation; the
wealthy are almost by definition economically fortunate. However, this is far
too quick.
Some of those who are economically fortunate may not be
wealthy at the time chosen for a one-off wealth tax. The economy is a dynamic
thing, full of flows (transfers) as well as stocks (wealth), and many
economically fortunate people will spend their large incomes quickly.
Conversely, some people who are not particularly economically fortunate will
have a strong preference to save, perhaps due their preferences about when they
wish to spend or because they are very risk-averse. A wealth tax will fall
heavily on savers and less heavily on spenders, and these categories do not
necessarily match up with levels of economic fortune.
I therefore tend to oppose wealth taxes. However, I would
not rule them out. If there is a crisis which means the state needs quick funds
then a wealth tax may be necessary if the alternative is default. I would also
suggest that they can be justified where the past economic regime has been
unjust and there are costs in switching to a just regime; it seems acceptable
that those who were benefiting from the past injustice should provide the
revenue required for the change. Finally, very low wealth taxes can be used as
a backstop where it is not possible to tax income. The idea, proposed by Deborah Schenk
is to set the tax rate as a proportion of the expected return to investment. So if a 20% desired investor tax-rate were
not possible and investment returns of 2% a year are expected then a wealth tax
of 0.4% would provide a rough proxy.
I have presented some acceptable forms of justifications for wealth tax, but in general I am against them. People have legitimate
expectations regarding their property and the state should be enabling people
to make and carry out plans. It does not matter if those plans involve spending
or saving. A wealth tax interferes with the plans that savers have made, making
their lives harder not easier. Equally importantly, it does not reliably fall
on the economically fortunate.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)