In my previous post I pointed out that specifying the
underlying basis desert raises difficult questions for supporters of desert
theory. However, they can (and do) just bite these bullets. However, there is a
more fundamental problem with the desert-based approach to economic justice.
This argument is best put (and as far as I know
originated from) by economist and philosopher Amartya Sen in a 1982 NY
Review of Books article “Just Deserts.” The relevant part of the article is
behind the paywall so I will summarize and quote it.
Sen accepts that if people are independent
producers—where each consumes what they have made without coming across others—then
we would accept that each could be seen to deserve what they have produced. However,
in a society where lots of people contribute to the social product in all sorts
of ways this simple link breaks down.
As Sen puts it “the personal production [desert] view is
difficult to sustain in cases of interdependent production, i.e., in almost all
the usual cases of production. Production is based on the joint use of
different resources, possibly provided by different people, and it is not
possible to separate out who—or even which resource—produced how much of the
total output.” (Sen, 1982 p4)
Sen considers whether marginal product can really do the job and argues that while
marginal product is “useful for deciding how to use additional resources so as
to maximize profit…it does not “show” which resource has “produced” how much of
the total output.” To support the argument he highlights that relative incomes
received for producing different goods will depend upon the arbitrary
difference in prices of the products. Therefore two people might produce “the
same two goods in unchanged amounts in exactly the same way, but a change in
the relative prices of our respective products…can make our relative incomes
change without any change of anything that you and I are, in fact, doing or
producing.” (Sen, 1982 p4)
Sen’s article is a review of P.T. Bauer’s book on
international development and so he illustrates his example of the difference
between workers in rich and poor countries. He points out that and “Indian
barber or circus performer may not be producing any less than a British barber
or circus performer—just the opposite if I am any judge—but will certainly earn
a great deal less.” (Sen, 1982 pp 4-5)
Put differently, we can say that the link between even
the productivity/economic contribution desert base and incomes determined in
the market is too tenuous to justify anything. If the market determines that a
banker needs to be paid £1m a year while a nurse is worth £27k this does not
mean that one deserves more than another. In a complex economy each person
occupies a position where their income depends upon numerous variables, most of
which are morally arbitrary.
The desert theorist needs to find a way to bridge between
the desert base and people’s incomes. Most desert theorists are supporters of
the market as a means to calculate what people deserve. They wish to build a
bridge from market incomes to desert to show that these incomes are deserved.
However, I think that such a bridge would be built on very shaky foundations.
The alternative is to use a desert base as a foundation
and from there build to a deserved share of social resources. That is, to start
from a desert base and build a bridge to the income that people deserve. This
could be seen to ignore market outcomes altogether and focus on the desert base
directly, though the productivity/contribution desert base is sometimes assumed
(wrongly) to ring the two together. So if we could measure people’s effort or
sacrifice we would just divide the product up accordingly. But this would then
make the concerns I presented with those desert bases all the more pressing.
I am sceptical that it is possible to rescue a desert
theory of economic justice from these concerns. However, in my subsequent blog I
will present what I think would be the most plausible available desert approach
to justice.
* You might get the argument that the doting daughter or
niece deserves the large inheritance because they tended to their relative when
others did not. However, this fails to distinguish between the carer who helps
a billionaire from one who helps a pauper.
No comments:
Post a Comment