Friday, 4 November 2016

Oxford University Press festival of philosophy

For the next week there will be a series of philosophy events taking place in Oxford. 

These have been organised by Oxford University Press along with the Oxford University Department for Continuing Education and Blackwell’s bookshop.

Next Saturday at 10.30 I will be on a panel discussing equality at Blackwell’s bookshop on Broad Street Oxford.

I’ve just been told it is fully booked but it might be worth contacting the organisers anyway or showing up on the day if you are particularly interested.


There are lots of other interesting events taking place as well.

Wednesday, 10 August 2016

Doff your caps to the new lord

Yesterday the Duke of Westminster died. Apparently he had an £8.3bn estimated fortune.

Today's news is that there is a new Duke of Westminster, who has apparently got a £9bn fortune.

This is surprising news to anyone who is aware that there is a terrible estate tax which takes half of the wealth of the deceased.

The telegraph has conveniently told us how the Westminster's can avoid the taxes that 'regular' wealthy people pay using a trust for the benefit of future Westminster's. The Telegraph story isn't about how this is a huge scandal - a massive scam at the expense of you me and everyone else. It's about whether the reader could benefit from such a scheme (answer - no).

If the Westminsters (or Grosvenors or whatever) don't really own the money then they aren't actually worth the £9bn that is reported. But if they do really own the money they should be taxed like anyone else would be. It seems on the face of it like they do own it and benefit from it.

Not only does this structure avoid the £3.6bn in tax that anyone else would expect to go to the treasury but actually tax on unearned fortunes should be MUCH higher than it is. Unearned income is simply the best thing to tax from both an economic and a moral point of view. It doesn't really disincentivise economically beneficial behaviour.

The outgoing duke seemed to be aware of all this himself - showing a sense of humour about his investment acumen. No reports as yet that he decided to bequeath the £3.6bn to the UK treasury though.

It seems feudalism is alive and well in 21st century Britain and it is totally sickening.

Tuesday, 3 May 2016

EU Referendum

I’m not particularly enamoured with the EU. The institution suffers from a democratic deficit, with a lot of decision making done by appointed officials who are very tenuously accountable to the people they serve.

Nevertheless, I’m entirely unconvinced by those who support Britain leaving the UK. For the most part, they strike me as a mixture of fantasists and xenophobes.

Just as the SNP promised to be everything to everyone in the Scottish independence referendum, so it is with the campaign(s) to leave. The campaigners tend to hold extreme views and do not like the EU as it blocks them from obtaining the outcome they want. These are usually right wing views but in some cases far-left views too.

Despite some having strong beliefs to the contrary, I'm doubtful that the UK would be turned into a goods-exporting, innovative, tax-haven, socialist utopia if we could only be free of EU shackles.

It is much more likely that leaving the EU would cause huge economic disruption and diminish the place of the UK in the wider world. Some supporters of leaving the EU might legitimately claim that this would be a price worth paying for greater self-determination and democracy. This is one argument I can respect, but I’m not sure how many anti-EU campaigners would really believe this.

This is because I don’t think the political system in the UK is a particularly good version of democracy. Our system of local representation was no doubt the best feasible one in the 17th century but it doesn’t really stand up to scrutiny in the 21st century. Instead of horse-drawn carts and mass-illiteracy we now have instantaneous communications and political parties (with their whips).

If the leave campaign were really interested in democracy I would expect the campaign to coincide strongly with those who also campaign for radical changes to our electoral system. To the contrary, I don’t get the impression many anti-EU campaigners really care about democratic legitimacy.

One problem with the democracy-based leave campaign is that if you leave the EU you can’t influence it any more to make it more democratic. Furthermore, the challenges facing the world are increasingly ones that require international agreement and co-operation, such as combating climate change.

I also wouldn't be convinced because I think it is sensible to limit what can be done in the name of the people, whether this would be suppressing the rights of individuals or minority groups, or, in making decisions that will be hugely counterproductive and self-defeating.


There is a pro-democracy argument for leaving the EU. However, I don’t think it is the one that motivates most anti-EU activists and nor is it one that convinces me. 

Sunday, 17 April 2016

Transparency of ownership and taxation

I’ve been very busy lately with my day job and doing teaching preparation but I’ve been trying to follow the #panamapapers information and commentary as best I can.

I have only managed to tweet a few things about it but I wanted to outline how I think there should be hugely more transparency about who owns what around the world, but a few limits on this.  

Transparency of company ownership

The system of property ownership is a human institution and should be organised in a fair way. The only way to know if it is fair is to know who owns what and to be sure that everyone is paying as much tax on it as they should. This is never going to be a perfect system – criminals and corrupt officials will always find ways to launder their ill-gotten gains. However, the system should be such that it is made difficult for them to do so and that there is a chance they will be caught out later on.

Many of the resources in the world are owned by corporate enterprises, which is perfectly understandable. Corporations go about the business of producing the goods and services that we all need and want.

But who owns the companies? Companies exist to benefit their ultimate owners, which is again perfectly fine. However, this means that the benefits are going to one or a mixture of the following:
·         Individuals (or family units) – could be sole-owners, partners, shareholders or workers with a stake in the company.
·         Governments
·         Sovereign wealth funds for the benefit of future generations within a country
·         Non-governmental Organisations (non-profit organisations)

The ultimate beneficial owners of corporate entities should be public information. The same should apply to trusts.

Transparency of personal tax records

After the Panamanian revelations politicians in the UK have been reluctantly releasing their tax records in order to prove that they are not receiving funds that undermine their credibility.

Some people are now suggesting that the UK should follow a Scandinavian model whereby tax records are publicly available.

I am in favour of greater transparency of personal tax records but not making full records available as politicians have been. The limited records I would suggest is simply gross income and tax paid in the last year and gross income and tax paid in their lifetime.

My suggestion is that there should be a website in which anyone can find out certain headline information about the taxpayers at
·         Any given address (but without specific names, so it would just list taxpayer 1, taxpayer 2 etc.)
·       The information for any given individual if three or more can be provided to anyone with the following pieces of information can be entered:
Surname
First Name
Address/Post code
Date of Birth
Tax number (National Insurance number in the UK)

This means that journalists or the public could find out information about well-known people as their date of births. 

Are there downsides to this transparency?

Public figures might feel forced to give further information to show where they got their income from. This might be intrusive, but on the other hand it seems important if people have disproportionately more cultural or political power in a society that the public is aware of their financial situation.

Self-employed people might not be happy that their competitors and clients can find out their income and possibly gain an advantage in negotiations as a result. However, I’ve said headline summary figures should be provided about companies and individuals so this wouldn’t necessarily tell you everything required in order to draw absolute conclusions.

Could it put people in danger?

The following groups could be in danger, but I will suggest ways around this:
·         Spies
But these could presumably be designated civil servants and self-employed business people as they no doubt already are to some degree to cover their identities.
·         Political refugees
Could be given new legal identities or have their addresses supressed under UN orders.
·         People whose lives are threatened (for example people who have stalkers/subject to religious persecution and fatwa’s/ in witness relocation)
Could also receive special protection on their information.


Overall, I think the benefits of greater transparency outweigh the downsides, but I'm keen to hear if there are any strong arguments I haven't considered.

Monday, 28 March 2016

Socialism/Communism and Scale

I've just read a very interesting draft article by Canadian philosopher Joseph Heath.

I don't always agree with Heath, but his work is usually very challenging (in a good way - i.e. interesting).

It is currently available on his academia.edu page, though he may remove this in the future if it gets reviewed and published.

His argument is that just as computer architecture has to be able to cope with the amount of data required of it so social relations must be able to cope with the amount and nature of social and economic interactions.

He discusses GA Cohen's well known short book 'Why not socialism?' in which Cohen points out that camping trips work fine without a market so why can't society? (He even indicates the reasons why it wouldn't in his book so it isn't a very effective analogy in its own terms).

Heath goes to the trouble of pointing out why - small scale societies have methods to work and these are attractive to us. Which is unsurprising as much of our genetic ancestry would have been based in such societies.

However, the way that these societies function is simply not scalable past about 150 people. So attempts to bring about socialism on a larger scale inevitably result in the kinds of terrible things that Mao and Stalin did in the hope of enforcing their utopia.

Heath is certainly no market fundamentalist - all the other work I have read by him has challenged market thinking (Cattalactic bias as he calls it). However, he concludes that on a social scale markets are a very effective method of allowing economies to function on a huge scale and so capitalism is therefore the normatively required economic system for advanced societies.

Heath's argument is a development of the common conclusion most people have reached (that communism isn't viable for societies of more than 150 people) but he has developed an interesting and well-researched way of presenting it.

Sunday, 13 March 2016

A journal article by yours truly - Arguing for a New Form of Taxation: Lifetime Hourly Averaging

Great news, my paper Arguing for a New Form of Taxation: Lifetime Hourly Averaging is available for viewing online.

I'm very pleased to have this paper published in the Journal of Applied Philosophy.

In the paper I present my lifetime hourly averaging proposal and defend hypothetical insurance as the best method to determine whether resources in society are distributed in a fair manner.

The hypothetical insurance approach is to consider how much redistribution people would support if they did not know if they had a good or bad upbringing, were highly talented or less talented and whether they find themselves in the right place at the right time to earn more money.

I argue that if people put themselves in this hypothetical situation they would find my hourly averaging tax and benefit proposal the most attractive one to transfer resources from the more to the less economically fortunate.

As I've explained elsewhere, you don't have to take a hypothetical insurance approach to support my hourly averaging proposals. However, in this paper I argue that hypothetical insurance is the best approach to take and that if you take this approach then hourly averaging is the tax and benefit system to support.

Monday, 8 February 2016

The end of big denominations

A new report from a team led by banker Peter Sands has suggested that large denomination notes should be discontinued. This is because the notes are used by those engaged in criminal activities and tax evasion (not the latter isn't criminal).

I'm generally a fan of the cashless society as I think it enables a better notion of who is doing what in the economy, which in turn allows for a fairer redistribution of resources.

It is hard to imagine any legitimate uses for large banknotes. The only time I can recall coming across one was seeing someone having theirs confiscated when trying to pay it into a bank - they had been conned in the pub.

Carrying around or otherwise transporting large amounts of cash seems very unsafe to me - for some reason I feel really on edge if I have over £50 in my wallet (do I think people can tell or something?)

Some people, including many commentators on the guardian article on the report, suggest that as the author used to be a banker it is clearly part of a bank-led plan to further take over. One worry is that we will be too dependent upon banks to go about our lives, where these banks might go bankrupt or whose service might be disrupted.

This is a worry and we need governments to ensure that they are ready to step in to ensure that banking services are working for all citizens. But then this leads people onto the next concern: banks and governments are two parts of an elite that wants greater control over us and blocking access to anonymous cash will give them that power.

One response would be to deny this possibility but I won't take that line. The threat of an Orwellian state which controls all resources via client banks and can monitor or shut down any individual if they get out of line is perfectly plausible. But the un-sexy response to this is to demand openness of government, to hold politicians and bureaucrats to account and to be very careful about who we vote for. (I.e. not the likes of Donald Trump and other populist "strong-men" who show disdain for checks and balances).

There is a real worry that in a social media age simplistic messages and solutions dominate difficult but reasoned analysis. But this makes it all the more important to respond appropriately.

After all, new technology is going to continue to play a larger role in our lives; we just need to make sure it works for all of us and not just a minority. Disrupting criminal activities, particularly tax evasion, is one such way it can.

Tuesday, 2 February 2016

Working time exactness

My hour credit proposals make use of hour credits, each of which is received when someone spends an hour. I'm sure some people doubt the feasibility of my proposal on the basis that employers wouldn't really control the time that workers to the required level of exactitude.

To challenge that I would usually point to time-card systems and computer-log-in-programmes that are used by many employers. I might also mention that the official leaving time where I work is 17.18.

But Morley College have gone a step further, A recent advert for an administrator there specified that the job is 0.700443 full-time-equivalent. So if a full week there is 38 hours a week then this job is 26.616834 hours per week, or 26 hours 37 minutes and 6 seconds.

Perhaps the time divides more neatly into whatever their specified full-time hours happen to be. However, I thought it was an interesting case, perhaps because of its apparent ridiculousness.

Sunday, 31 January 2016

Conclusion: Institutionalising the constructed desert base (8/8)

In my previous blog I presented a new form of desert base that I believe is more attractive than the traditional approaches to economic desert. I will conclude my series by considering the institutional implications of this.

1.       Implant and monitoring

If we could insert chips into everyone’s heads to measure reliably how much time, energy and dissatisfaction they are expending at a given point in time. They would also be monitored somehow so it can be known if they are engaging in economically productive activity. This technology could then monitor how much people are expending when they engage in productive activity we would be able to share out incomes accordingly. However, we cannot currently do this, and perhaps would worry about doing so—it might be quite invasive to follow people’s activities and mental states that closely.

2.       An endowment tax.

For the time being it would be easier (though still not that easy) to take account of people’s incomes, the time they expend and their abilities. Essentially, an endowment tax would be the most obvious stand-in for the constructed desert base.

This would tax people differently depending on their abilities so, where this is measured by test results, someone with top IQ and high school test results could be assigned to a higher tax band throughout the remainder of their life than those with lower scores. Even then the practicalities are difficult—how much weight should be given to the different measures such as mathematical vs. emotional intelligence, creativity vs rule-following etc.

Stuart White proposes a system which puts people into three categories to make this easier (see also chapters 4 & 5 of his book The Civic Minimum). However, while this makes the endowment tax much easier to administer and much less controversial it also reduces its effectiveness at taxing people according to the ability and therefore

There are several serious complaints against endowment taxation, such as that it would be invasive to test for this and that it would unfairly limit the talented. Some people have talked of the ‘slavery of the talented’ as talented people would not be able to take lower paid work that would be open to less talented individuals—the low paid work would not be enough to pay their higher endowment tax.

So if endowment is considered too difficult to accurately measure or if endowment taxes are considered unfair, what is the next-best option for the constructed desert base?

3.       Hourly averaging

I would suggest that my hourly averaging proposal is the next closest option to the constructed desert base. This system taxes those who receive large incomes after expending a small amount of time working and provides subsidies to those who work long hours for small rewards.

I have suggested that time spent working should be one of the factors in the desert base as it is something that people can control. One complaint might be that some people who work long hours do so in low-productivity activities which are do not make them deserving. However, in some cases this might be because the person cannot obtain more difficult higher paid work.

It is quite different from endowment taxation in that people with a lot of potential to contribute but who do not do so will not be penalised. However, it may not be that someone who has more potential finds a particular job easier than others and therefore render them less deserving. It might be that someone with the potential to be a lawyer finds being a waitress just as stressful as the person who would struggle to master legal procedure.

I would also add that my CLIPH-rate tax system which combines hourly averaging with a comprehensive tax on personal gains would track the desert base very well. This is because each person’s income would be tied to the number of hours they have worked in their lifetime, and those who have not worked would have their unearned income taxed at 100%.

The downside of the CLIPH-rate tax is that it would not be able to distinguish readily between two people who receive large hourly incomes due to the sacrifice involved vs. earning rents on their skills and talents. However, one factor is the way that prices will react to the tax—those who earn large incomes from rents will not require more pay when the tax would be introduced. On the other hand, jobs which people would be unwilling to do when taxes rise substantially are likely to be those which are both productive and involving a lot of sacrifice.

So a variation of the hour-credit system proposes itself. Those jobs which begin to go unfilled with the introduction of hourly averaging could be ones for which workers could receive ‘bonus hour credits’ as a way to recognise their sacrifice. Dangerous work such as deep sea diving might be one example of this—people might be happy to take these risks if they thereby earn a large net income and have a lot of leisure time to enjoy it.

Conclusion

I began this series of blogs explaining that some people find deservingness the appropriate way to determine how much each person should receive from their society. I explained the existing theories of economic desert which begin either from desert bases or from market earnings and why these are all problematic despite their various attractions. After highlighting the various links between economic desert and markets I proposed a new form of desert base constructed from the intuitively attractive elements of the existing desert bases. In this final blog I have considered the options to institutionalise the constructed desert base. I still remain sceptical of building economic justice from desert but I would challenge those who do to propose a more feasible and less controversial way to give people what they deserve than the CLIPH-rate tax.


Thursday, 28 January 2016

Creating a plausible desert base

In my previous blogs I have outlined problems with the three main bases for economic desert and argued that making a direct link between market prices and desert is inherently problematic. In this blog I will present what I believe is a fairer desert base. This desert base utilises both desert bases and market prices, but as part of a wider desert equation. Essentially the idea is to construct a desert base by putting together the best parts of existing proposals.

The fair desert base is to give each person weighted share of social product which accounts for their personal sacrifice (encompassing time, effort, danger, stressfulness and risk of harm) expended in productive enterprise (accounting for the effectiveness of that enterprise and whether they had the ability to contribute more than they have). I will refer to it as the constructed desert base but an alternative name for the proposed desert base is the ability-adjusted multifaceted base.

So for an individual (i) where d is deserved income, n is the number of people in society, r is the total amount of resources available for distribution in the given time-period, s is personal sacrifice compared to the average (where the average is 1), p is productivity,  m is the individual’s market income (compared to average where the average is 1) and a is the application of the person’s ability to the work that they do (compared to average where the average is 1), the constructed desert base would be something like:



Of course the actual weightings of the factors and the practicalities of assessing these components (particularly sacrifice) is more complicated than is indicated above. Furthermore, we might want to apply ability to many of the subcomponents. Some people might have more stamina and be able to work longer and harder while others have disabilities that reduce their capacity. Some people might be more able to deal with stress or responsibility or unpleasant working environments than others.

As I emphasised, people’s gross income will (in normal circumstances) go up if they take work requiring more personal sacrifice, as I outlined in my previous blog. It will also go up (again generally though not universally) if they engage in more productive work, and also if they make use of their ability. However, some people have a much wider menu of productive options available to them and so they may be able to earn more than others without making as much of a personal sacrifice.

For example, a top professional footballer may well have to train and play hard to retain their position. But they don’t work several hundred times as hard as a roofer. The relative difference in effort is much smaller than that of market income. If the roofer could play football at that level they would do so, certainly given the financial rewards. However, they do not have the required natural talent and so do not have the option. The different earnings between the two do not reflect a large difference in sacrifice but rather a large difference in ability.

Markets play an important and interesting role in the constructed desert base. As I pointed out in my previous blog, an individual will tend to earn more if they work longer, do less popular work, and do work whose products are more highly desired by others. In that sense, higher earnings imply a higher level of desert. However, at the same time, higher earnings often arise due to a higher ability to earn, which does not indicate greater deservingness.

Why is the constructed desert base a good way to link desert and income? It utilises a market test to distinguish people who sacrifice more to provide the goods and services that others value. However, it is not a slave to market valuations as it corrects for the influence of ability.

I think the constructed desert base would match most of the cases where people intuit that person x deserves more than person y. Of course, it won’t satisfy those who see desert through a purely market or single-based-desert approach to the issue. However, I have explained in previous blogs why these positions aren't really that attractive.

For the record, I would suggest that I think the scepticism I proposed about linking desert to economic outcomes still applies. I suggested that desert theories fail if they attempt to build a bridge either from a desert base to income or from market incomes to a desert base. My proposal, however, is to attempt to link the relevant factors in an interlocked manner which utilises the market and the existing plausible desert bases.

One possible criticism might be that my constructed desert base is not thereby a pre-institutional notion of desert. However, just because it is a constructed desert base this does not mean it cannot be pre-institutional; I am not proposing institutions and then judging the distribution on its closeness to those institutions. It is important to utilise the market so that a) the amount people deserve is linked to the total wealth available for distribution and b) there is a link between what consumers want and what producers deserve. In my next blog—the final in this series on desert—I will conclude by discussing the institutional implications of the constructed economic desert base.



Sunday, 24 January 2016

Desert bases and market income

So far in this series of blogs I have argued that there are serious problems when starting a theory of economic desert from either market incomes or the traditional desert bases. In this post I want to suggest that there is a link between the common desert bases and market income, even though it is not feasible to claim any simple and direct link between the two.

If we consider the three desert bases outlined previously we can see that they will, in most circumstances, have a strong influence on someone’s income.

Effort: If someone puts in more or less effort across their working life then we would expect their lifetime income to rise accordingly. This will be particularly true of people who are self-employed or paid for piecework, but we would even expect it for people in salaried jobs as their harder work may be noticed by superiors who will be keen to retain or even promote them.

Contribution: This desert base is often considered to be directly related to market income and so it is not controversial to claim that greater contribution will bring about greater market incomes.

Compensation: The labour market should also lead people to be rewarded more if they sacrifice more. People who work in more stressful, dangerous or unpleasant jobs get paid more than those with similar skills and talents doing less difficult work. In the UK an investment banker will get paid more than someone in the human resources department of a bank, a deep sea diver will be paid more than a teacher and a bin-collector will get paid more than a labourer.

The point is not universal. There may be people who put in lot of effort but in an undirected manner and would be more successful if they relaxed and slept more or slowed down and reflected more. Similarly, people’s sacrifices may sometimes go unrewarded, for example if they are the hardest working person in a large team where the rewards are shared out equally or where a lot of people only have less enjoyable work available to them such that wages are low.

Contributions to the economy (and certainly society in a wider sense) do not always result in market rewards. Some people may contribute a lot in a way that is not recognised by the market—such as charitable work or caring. Additionally, there may be people who obtain a very high income without contributing very much at all—such as those who find a legal loophole which they can exploit to make money.

However, while it is not a universal rule that income goes up for those who act according to each desert base, for the most part the person will be rewarded in the market for their activities.

What I wish to highlight in this blog is that there is a link between market rewards and all of the economic desert bases. The link is sometimes quite weak, since market incomes depend upon supply and demand rather than acts in accordance with desert bases. Nevertheless I think it is important to note this and how this fact should lead us to reassess our views of the desert approach to economic justice.

1.       Has the link caused some to find the pro-market aspect of the desert approach more plausible than it is?
2.       Has the link caused some people who are pro-market to seek to find a desert base that supports their preferred view?
3.       Does the link mean that anti-capitalists who take a desert-based approach to justice should be more pro-market than they are?
and:
4.       Does the link imply that the most plausible desert base will take account of (or make use of) market pricing, though not be identical with it?

Along with these, there may also be other interesting questions that follow from the relationship I’ve highlighted between desert bases and the market. However, I will focus on the fourth of the above in my next blog, where I will construct a more complex alternative desert base which I believe is much more plausible than the approaches I’ve presented so far.



Monday, 18 January 2016

What is the problem with desert?

In my previous post I pointed out that specifying the underlying basis desert raises difficult questions for supporters of desert theory. However, they can (and do) just bite these bullets. However, there is a more fundamental problem with the desert-based approach to economic justice.

This argument is best put (and as far as I know originated from) by economist and philosopher Amartya Sen in a 1982 NY Review of Books article “Just Deserts.” The relevant part of the article is behind the paywall so I will summarize and quote it.

Sen accepts that if people are independent producers—where each consumes what they have made without coming across others—then we would accept that each could be seen to deserve what they have produced. However, in a society where lots of people contribute to the social product in all sorts of ways this simple link breaks down.

As Sen puts it “the personal production [desert] view is difficult to sustain in cases of interdependent production, i.e., in almost all the usual cases of production. Production is based on the joint use of different resources, possibly provided by different people, and it is not possible to separate out who—or even which resource—produced how much of the total output.” (Sen, 1982 p4)

Sen considers whether marginal product can really do the job and argues that while marginal product is “useful for deciding how to use additional resources so as to maximize profit…it does not “show” which resource has “produced” how much of the total output.” To support the argument he highlights that relative incomes received for producing different goods will depend upon the arbitrary difference in prices of the products. Therefore two people might produce “the same two goods in unchanged amounts in exactly the same way, but a change in the relative prices of our respective products…can make our relative incomes change without any change of anything that you and I are, in fact, doing or producing.” (Sen, 1982 p4)

Sen’s article is a review of P.T. Bauer’s book on international development and so he illustrates his example of the difference between workers in rich and poor countries. He points out that and “Indian barber or circus performer may not be producing any less than a British barber or circus performer—just the opposite if I am any judge—but will certainly earn a great deal less.” (Sen, 1982 pp 4-5)

Put differently, we can say that the link between even the productivity/economic contribution desert base and incomes determined in the market is too tenuous to justify anything. If the market determines that a banker needs to be paid £1m a year while a nurse is worth £27k this does not mean that one deserves more than another. In a complex economy each person occupies a position where their income depends upon numerous variables, most of which are morally arbitrary.

The desert theorist needs to find a way to bridge between the desert base and people’s incomes. Most desert theorists are supporters of the market as a means to calculate what people deserve. They wish to build a bridge from market incomes to desert to show that these incomes are deserved. However, I think that such a bridge would be built on very shaky foundations.

The alternative is to use a desert base as a foundation and from there build to a deserved share of social resources. That is, to start from a desert base and build a bridge to the income that people deserve. This could be seen to ignore market outcomes altogether and focus on the desert base directly, though the productivity/contribution desert base is sometimes assumed (wrongly) to ring the two together. So if we could measure people’s effort or sacrifice we would just divide the product up accordingly. But this would then make the concerns I presented with those desert bases all the more pressing.

I am sceptical that it is possible to rescue a desert theory of economic justice from these concerns. However, in my subsequent blog I will present what I think would be the most plausible available desert approach to justice.


* You might get the argument that the doting daughter or niece deserves the large inheritance because they tended to their relative when others did not. However, this fails to distinguish between the carer who helps a billionaire from one who helps a pauper. 

Sunday, 17 January 2016

The merits of meritocracy

Most supporters of the desert approach to economic justice are attracted to it because it is entirely meritocratic. People get a share of social goods to the extent that they merit them (according to the relevant, though inevitably controversial, desert base chosen from those described in my previous blog).

Meritocracy appears to lend itself to the free market in some ways but not others. In common with pro-free-market entitlement theories of justice such as libertarianism, workers should get the product of their efforts. Taxes on labour are to be avoided and the free market in the field of production should be encouraged (or replicated if the economy is a command rather than market-based one).

However, in other areas desert theory is diametrically opposed to free-market entitlement theories. According to libertarianism people should be able to give away their resources to others without interference. However, recipients of gifts and inheritances have not done anything *and should not therefore receive this. Any resources not used by the deserving recipient should be returned to the social pot for distribution to the deserving.

Meritocracy is preferable to libertarianism because it links income to what the individual does rather than the vagaries of their family fortune. However, I would still question whether meritocracy is really that meritocratic. Family background could still play a role in a desert-based economy as some parents will be more nurturing than others. People also have different natural talents which they can utilise in the labour market to earn more than others, with the further issue that all sorts of pieces of good fortune can make a huge difference to people’s lifetime earnings. The person who gets a particular experience or opportunity might make the most of it, but the people who missed out on it would have made the most of it as well if they had the chance.

Saturday, 16 January 2016

Economic desert bases

People who complain that society "gives x more than they deserve" and "gives y less than they deserve" presumably have some basis for making this judgment. We can take this question one step back and ask the underlying basis for this. We call this the desert base.

Essentially, a desert base is the underlying thing which determines what people deserve. For winning the best leading actor oscar the base is providing the most impressive acting performance in an eligible film. However, where it comes to economic desert agreement about the ideal base is lacking.

The three most commonly cited desert bases are:

·         Effort (people who work hard deserve more than the lazy)
·         Contribution/Productivity (people who make a larger contribution to society should get more)
·         Compensation (people who give up more should get more)

However, there are problems with each of these bases:

To reward people for the effort they make opens the question as to what activities should count as ones which efforts count. If I put a lot of effort into playing football with my friends this presumably doesn’t mean I deserve as much as someone who works hard as a paramedic. However, does this mean that the professional footballer is also undeserving? Presumably there would have to be a threshold at which point people’s activities become ‘work’ and thereby qualify them as deserving.

But this means that a particularly hard working lower division footballer is as deserving as a premier league one. Perhaps they are, but this raises further concerns about the incentives that such a system creates. If only your efforts determine your rewards then this reduces the pressure to increase productivity or for people to do work that they are more suited to—natural footballers would be better off playing rugby and vice versa so that both are putting in extra effort. Indeed people might find the work they would be best at easier and taking that work might make them worse off.

To reward people according to their contribution, on the other hand, would provide very good incentives for people. Someone who provides goods and services that are more valued by others (according to how much they are willing to pay for them) will receive more. One major concern with this is that it does not seem fair to reward people according to their productivity. Some people are more naturally talented than others and such people would be able to contribute more than others.

The third prominent approach could be seen as a solution to the two problems above. By providing people compensation for their activities in the name of the social product this would seem to take account of the effort that people put in but also allows for further sacrifices that people make that do not fall under the heading of effort. So someone who takes a particularly risky (though not otherwise taxing) job might be deserving of greater reward. It gets around the talent issue to a degree because people who find a job easier due to their talent would deserve less than their colleagues who find it difficult.

However, the compensation approach still shares a lot of the issues with the effort approach. People who suffer more for the economic produce because of their inefficiency would be more deserving than others. This again discourages people from doing work to which they are most suited and from making productivity gains.

Supporters of their preferred desert base can just bite the bullets presented above. However, specifying the potential underlying desert bases can draw out problems that might not occur to those who unreflectively adopt a desert-approach to economic justice.

In the next blog I will present a more fundamental reason to doubt the applicability of desert to economic justice. 

Tuesday, 5 January 2016

What is desert?

The topic of this series of blogs is the desert-based approach to economic justice. Put simply this approach says that economic resources should be distributed to individuals in accordance with the relevant facts about them.

One way to further distinguish desert-based theories is to say that they imply a notion of pre-institutional desert. After all, all approaches to economic justice will allow a judgment of whether a particular individual has received what they deserve. However, for these other theories the judgment about desert is a secondary one.

For institutional claims of desert the assertion that people deserve x is derived without reference to desert. In pre-institutional theories of desert, on the other hand, desert is itself the basis of the judgment of justice.

People can make use of the notion of desert in all sorts of situations, for example “the team who trained hardest deserved to win the tournament” or “the student who studied very diligently deserved to obtain the highest mark.” Where the institution defines the desert there is no controversy because the person deserves what the institutional rules say what each should obtain. Similarly, in cases where there is a clear basis for the activity—such as being able to play a piece of music accurately but expressively—then we can rank people’s deservingness of prizes in accordance with their performance.


If we have an underlying notion of desert that readily tells us what everyone in society should get then this would be a very strong basis for fairly distributing resources. Desert theory therefore needs to answer two questions a) what is the proper basis underlying economic desert claims? and b) how can this basis translate into a monetary amount? I will consider these issues in my next two blogs.

Sunday, 3 January 2016

On desert (1/1)

I have long wanted to blog about economic desert and I am finally getting around to doing so. I would love to write an academic paper about this but a blog series should be less time-consuming and have a wider potential audience.

Sometimes people complain that they or others have not received what they deserve. It is a more common complaint from right-wingers, who sometimes claim that entrepreneurs and high-earners lose out on what they deserve due to taxation. On the other side, left-wingers will claim that working people do not get what they deserve for their time and efforts.

Not many political philosophers advocate a desert-based theory of economic justice for reasons I will describe in a later blog. However, some of those who do have a more sophisticated position than the unreflective cries of unfairness outlined above. David Miller is one such prominent thinker, and he advocates a form of market socialism whereby worker-owned firms would compete in a marketplace and the workers would get the benefits of the work they do.


In this series of blogs I will explain the desert-based approach to justice and outline why it is considered attractive and yet problematic. I will then suggest a new way of linking desert and the market that would, I believe, provide the most plausible theory of economic desert.  I will conclude by highlighting how this would fit very well with my CLIPH-rate tax proposals.