Showing posts with label meritocracy. Show all posts
Showing posts with label meritocracy. Show all posts

Wednesday, 5 January 2022

Equality of Opportunity and Discrimination Materials

This coming term I will be teaching a new course for the general public on some overlapping issues relating to justice that I thought would work well together. 

The online course Equality of Opportunity and the Ethics of Discrimination covers some lingering issues of controversy about how society should respond to unequal opportunity. There is even disagreement about what 'equality of opportunity' actually means, and whether it is really an important goal. 

You can read more about the course on the webpage

However, I thought I would share some useful background materials for those who might want to explore further, either in advance of taking the course or if you miss the course and want to investigate the topic. 

Online lectures

A good place to start with political philosophy is Michael Sandel’s Justice Course. Several lectures are directly relevant to this course topic, such as:

Lecture 14: A Deal Is A Deal  (You Tube direct link) and  Lecture 15: What’s A Fair Start? – Harvard Justice (You Tube link).

Tommie Shelby "Justice and Race" Blavatnik School of Government (2020)

Charles W. Mills "Theorizing Racial Justice" Tanner Lecture on Human Values (2020), or a video of his talk "Racial Equality" UCT (2014)

More advanced are Tim Scanlon's Uehiro Lectures, Oxford (2013). The third is “When Does Equality Matter? (lecture 3 – equality of opportunity)” but lectures one and two are useful and relevant as well.

Janet Radcliffe Richards' Uehiro Lectures, Oxford (2012) are also relevant. Again, the third is particularly relevant, but references arguments introduced in the previous two

When Does Equality Matter? (lecture 3 – equality of opportunity)” but lectures one and two are useful and relevant as well.

Scanlon builds on the work of his teacher John Rawls, and there are lots of lectures and podcasts about the work of Rawls, such as this Bryan Magee Interview with Ronald Dworkin “Rawls vs Nozick” (1978).

For podcasts, there is the 

Podcasts

The BBC Reith Lecture series by Kwame Anthony Appiah (2016) is worth a listen. 

Discrimination is ExpensiveThe Pie (2021)

Policy Matters “Discrimination in the labour market and what policymakers can do about itUniversity of Bath (2021)

Interview with Tarun Khaitan "Indirect Discrimination" Philosophy 247 

"Episode 9 - Understanding indirect discrimination" Mills & Reeve - Employment law Podcast (2017)

The Libertarian Podcast “Anti-Discrimination Laws Vs. Freedom of AssociationHoover Institution (2021)

Course books

The course does not have a single textbook, and those on the course will be provided with selected readings from several sources.

However, if you wanted to purchase a book for use alongside the course then you could go for one of the following, depending which of the three related topics you are particularly interested in:

  • Equality of opportunity, in which case you could buy Andrew Mason’s book “Levelling the playing field”
  • Discrimination, in which case you could buy Deborah Hellman’s “When is discrimination wrong?”
  • Affirmative action, in which case you could get either Cahn’s “The Affirmative Action Debate” or Cohen and Sterba’s “Affirmative Action and Racial Preferences: A Debate (Point/Counterpoint)” or Elizabeth Anderson's "The Imperative of Integration" (2011)

Meritocracy
The course does not focus on the issue of meritocracy, but it is certainly a relevant approach, and one that has been much discussed in recent times. 

Sandel, mentioned above, has recently published a book The Tyranny of Merit and. 
A few other recent books are available free to download:

Happy reading, watching and listening and I hope to see you on the course!

Monday, 8 January 2018

One rule for the rich...

A recent Washington Post piece by Elizabeth Breunig raises a lot of interesting points and is worth reading.
 
She highlights that in the US (as in the UK) there are constant moves to ensure that those receiving ever shrinking welfare payments are in fact working (or actively seeking work). This is sometimes referred to as 'workfare' 

Breunig points out that most of the non-working poor are elderly, children, or care-givers, all of whom seem to have some reason for not earning more in market employment.

What is particularly interesting about this piece is comparison between the treatment of the poor and rich non-workers.

Everyday libertarianism for the idle rich vs. workfare for the undeserving poor

This comparison might strike some as odd - the poor in question are receiving assistance from society via government spending while the idle rich in question aren't. They receive their money from dividends etc.

The author gives examples of policies that benefit investors and capital-holders, which could be considered subsidies for the idle rich. The point is that these subsidies do not come with a work-requirement as do workfare programmes

I think its possible to go further than this. Even if there weren’t such subsidies it would still be morally acceptable to insist that the idle rich work, even if their income comes from a “private” rather than a “public” source.

This is because the idea that there is a difference between the two is based upon a mistake, labelled everyday libertarianism by philosophers Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel in their excellent book The Myth of Ownership.

This is the idea that people are led to consider their gross income to be ‘theirs’ and that the tax system takes some of it from them. If you are a libertarian, then you might believe this to be the case. However, since libertarianism isn’t a very attractive political philosophy and since most people aren’t in fact libertarians it is an unfortunate but common mistake to make.  

It is more appropriate to consider the property distribution system holistically, and consider each owner (individual, corporation, charity or government) as the temporary holder of their property. There are strong reasons to let the owner have power of the property while they own it, of course, and I don’t draw the conclusion that the government should be able to seize property unless there is an exceptional circumstance (such as a national emergency, where the property is required for infrastructure development or where the property in question is illegal). I don’t go as far as more radical leftists who would then say that the above means that any private property can be seized by the government at any time.

The point is that when property is transferred from one owner to another it is an opportunity for society to consider whether to (in rare situations) block or (more commonly) tax the transaction. It may appear as if the transaction is just between the two parties involved, but in fact the whole of society is involved. Firstly, society supports the system in which the property and the transaction exists. Secondly, the value of the property exists because of the rest of society.

Investors aren’t just sitting on their property, they are sending it out into the world and getting more back. This is captured by my Comprehensive-Acquired-income tax-base. A self-sufficient farmer who tends their own land and gains from it wouldn’t have to pay tax on their gains. But no-one gets rich from being a self-sufficient farmer who does not engage economically with anyone else.

The idle rich person is then a recipient of social wealth in just the same way as the welfare/benefit recipient.

Why do we care whether people work?

There are lots of possible reasons why we might want to ensure that people work rather than receive money while being idle.

·       Social Consequences: If someone who could work doesn’t do so then this is a missed opportunity for society. Society could have got the benefit of this labour but misses out.

·       Paternalistic consequentialist: This is the idea that it is in people’s interest to work (whether they realise or not). This is because people who are idle will get into unhealthy habits, become slothful, lose purpose and so on.

·       Contributions are important: It is important for people (where able) to contribute to society, and people should only receive social wealth to the extent that they do contribute to society. Interestingly, desert-based (or meritocratic) theories of justice would be against all unearned wealth such as gifts and inheritances since these are unearned.

What is interesting is that these three justifications apply to the wealthy just as much as the poor.

An alternative justification is that people should do whatever they are required to do by the correct theory of justice. Some of those theories will require workfare, and they may or may not require wealthy individuals to work too. My preferred theory would require both. This is the correct way to think about it, and I encourage people to engage with such theories.

However, what about those who want to support workfare but not force the idle rich to work before they can receive unearned income?

To be consistent, anyone relying on any of the three arguments listed above also will have to apply this to wealthy individuals who choose not to work.

What is a contribution?

In the article, Breunig makes the point that carers can contribute to society without receiving market income. Furthermore, many clearly socially useful activities aren’t well-rewarded in the market (such as most minimum wage work), while some activities that aren’t as clearly socially useful are well-remunerated. This is because remuneration follows from supply as well as demand.

On the other hand, someone who inherits a fortune and lives off the returns from this obtains a market income without contributing. It would be possible to insist that only those who work should be able to receive unearned income, or that lifetime unearned income should be linked to the amount of work someone has performed.

Market income is not a perfect indicator of contribution. However, again, I don’t take the hard-left conclusion that market income is meaningless.

Nevertheless, there is often some correlation between market income and social contribution, something I mentioned in my blogs on desert-theories of justice. The point is that we can look at a broad conception of contribution as participation in the labour market or undertaking some socially useful activity such as studying or caring.

Workfare for the rich?

So, do we need to insist on workfare for rich investors as well as the poor?

I think so, on the basis that this would make for a fairer society. My CLIPH-rate tax system would link people’s net income to the hours they have worked (or undertaken some equivalent or having been excused from doing so).

However, those who argue for workfare on more limited grounds, such as the three arguments listed above, should also support workfare for the idle rich on the same grounds. This would presumably mean taxing non-working but able people from gaining unearned income through punitive taxation or by blocking such benefits until the individual has undertaken the requisite about of work.

How else could they avoid the inconsistency?

·       They could stop insisting on workfare and instead support a Universal Basic Income, i.e. to give up on workfare.
·       They could advocate a theory of justice which justifies workfare programmes for the poor but not the rich. This rules-out desert or contribution-based theories. Furthermore, it probably also rules-out consequentialist theories which emphasise economically strong outcomes.


As I mentioned, my proposal is to link net income and work for all those who can work. This applies whether they are wealthy or poor, high-earner or low-earner. 

Sunday, 17 January 2016

The merits of meritocracy

Most supporters of the desert approach to economic justice are attracted to it because it is entirely meritocratic. People get a share of social goods to the extent that they merit them (according to the relevant, though inevitably controversial, desert base chosen from those described in my previous blog).

Meritocracy appears to lend itself to the free market in some ways but not others. In common with pro-free-market entitlement theories of justice such as libertarianism, workers should get the product of their efforts. Taxes on labour are to be avoided and the free market in the field of production should be encouraged (or replicated if the economy is a command rather than market-based one).

However, in other areas desert theory is diametrically opposed to free-market entitlement theories. According to libertarianism people should be able to give away their resources to others without interference. However, recipients of gifts and inheritances have not done anything *and should not therefore receive this. Any resources not used by the deserving recipient should be returned to the social pot for distribution to the deserving.

Meritocracy is preferable to libertarianism because it links income to what the individual does rather than the vagaries of their family fortune. However, I would still question whether meritocracy is really that meritocratic. Family background could still play a role in a desert-based economy as some parents will be more nurturing than others. People also have different natural talents which they can utilise in the labour market to earn more than others, with the further issue that all sorts of pieces of good fortune can make a huge difference to people’s lifetime earnings. The person who gets a particular experience or opportunity might make the most of it, but the people who missed out on it would have made the most of it as well if they had the chance.